Page:Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology (1870) - Volume 1.djvu/619

From Wikisource
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This page needs to be proofread.
loc cit.
loc cit.

CAPITO. OfAntislitis Labeo. 0/ C. Ateius CfipUo. M. Cocceius Nerva Masurius Sabiiius. pater. C. Cassius Longinus. Serapronius Proculus. Longinus, Nerva filius. Caelius Sabinus. Pegasus. Priscus Javolenus. P. Juventius Celsus Aburnus Valeus. pater. Tuscianus. Celsus filius. Salvias Julianus. Neratius Priscus. To the list of Capito's followers may be added with certainty. Gaius ; with the highest probability, Pomponius ; and, with more or less plausible con- jecture, a few others, as T. Aristo. The schools, of which Capito and Labeo were the founders, took their respective names from distin- guished disciples of those jurists. The followers of Capito were called from Masurius Sabi- nus, Sabiniani ; and afterwards, from Cassius Longinus, Cissiani. The followers of Labeo took from Proculus (not Proculeius), the ill-fonncd name Proculeiani (so spelt, not Proculiani, in all old manuscripts wherever it occurs). From a mis- understanding of the phrase Pegasianum jus, (meaning, the legal writings of Pegasus,) in the scholiast on Juvenal (iv. 77), some have supposed that the followers of Labeo were also c;dled from Pegasus, Pegasiani. {Diet, of Aiit.s.v.Jurisconsulii.) The controversy as to the characteristic differ- ences between these schools has been endless, and most writers on the subject have endeavoured to refer those differences to some general principle. When continental jurists were disputing about the relative importance of equity, as compared with strict law, the Roman schools were supposed to be biised upon a disagreement between the admirers of equity and the admirers of strictness. Those who thought Labeo the better man were anxious to en- list him upon their side of the question. Accord- ing to Mascovius and Horamel, Labeo was the ad- vocate of sound and strict interpretation ; accor- ding to Bach and Tydemann, Capito was an oppo- nent of that enlightened equity which seeks to penetrate beyond the literal husky rind. When modem jurists were divided into the philosophical (dyslogistically, unhistorical), and the historical (dyslogistically, unphilosophical), schools, Capito and L;ibeo were made to belong to one or other of these parties. Dirksen {lieitrdge zur Kcntniss des Romischen IiecIiis,TpTp. 1-139) and Zimmern (Ji.R. G. . $ 66) think, that the schools differ chiefl}' in their mode of handling legal questions ; that the votaries of Sabinus look for something extenial to hang their reasoning upon, whether it be ancient practice, or the text of a law, or the words of a private disposition, or analogy to a positive rule, and only at last, in default of all these, resort to the general principles of right and the natural feelings of equity : whereas the votaries of Procu- lus on the other hand, looking, in the first instance, more freely to the inner essence of rules and insti- tutions, and anxious to construct law on the un- changing basis of morality, sometimes by an appa- rent deviation from the letter, arrive at results more con-espondent with the nature of the subject. Puchta {Inst. 1. § 98) refers the on'ginal divergence to the personal characters of the founders, the ac- quiescence of Capito in received doctrines, the liberal and comprehensive intellect of Labeo, urging philosophical progress and scientific developcment. Whether the original differences rested on CAPITO. 601 general pnnciples, or whether they consisted in discordant opinions upon isolated particular points, it is clear that the political opjjosition between Capito and Labeo had not long any important in- fluence on their respective schools, for Cocceius Nerva, the immediate successor of Labeo, did not adopt the political opinions of his master, which, as the empire became consolidated, must have soon grown out of fashion, the more especially, since jurists now began to receive their authorization from the prince. Proculus was a still stronger im- perialist than Nerva. Even in private law, the subsequent leaders on either side modified, per- haps considerably, the original diflferences, and introduced new matters of discussion. The dis- tinction of the schools is strongly manifested in Gaius, who wrote under Antoninus Pius, but soon after that time it seems to have worn out from the influence of independent eclecticism. Even in earlier times, a jurist was not necessarily a bigoted supporter of every dogma of his school. Thus, we find a case in Gaius (iii. 140) where Cassius approves the opinion of Labeo, while Proculus follows that of Ofilius, the master of Capito. 'Not every question, on which the opinions of Roman jurists were divided, was a school question. When Justinian found it necessary to settle fifty disputed questions in the interval between the first and second editions of his Constitutionum Codex, he was obliged to look back to ancient contro- versies, and sometimes to annul by express sanc- tion that which was already antiquated in practice. The consideration of this fact alone shews that, from his L. Decisiones, it would be wrong to infer, as some have done, that the old separation of the schools existed in his time ; but further, there is no proof that any of the questions he settled were ever party questions of the schools. Though the distinctions of the schools gradually wore out, as eminent and original men arose, who thought for themselves, there is no proof that there was ever a distinct middle school. A school of Miscelliones has been imagined in consequence of a passage of Festus, which, however, has nothing to do with the profession of the law : " Miscelliones appellantur, qui non certae sunt sententiae, sed variorum mixtorumque judiciorum." Cujas, from a false reading of Servius {ad Virg. Aen. iii. 68), imagined the existence of an eclectic sect of Her- ciscundi. Servius, speaking of the opinions of the ancients concerning the soul, says that some be- lieved that consciousness ceased with death ; others, that the soul was inunortal ; while the Stoics, pur- suing a middle course, held that it was buiied in Vie earth, and lived as long as the body endured.

  • ' Stoici vero, terris cotidi, i. e. medium secuti, tam

diu durare dicunt, quamdiu durat et corpus." Cujas, for terris condi, deciphered, as he thought, in his nearly illegible copj', herciscundi, a technical word, which appears in the Familiae herciscundae causa. (Dig. 10. tit. 2.) The error of Cujas, in referring a name so strangely gotten to an eclectic sect of Roman jurists, gained genei-al reception among the civilians of his day, on account of bin great learning and authority. Though Capito is little quoted — not once by his own follower, Gaius — though there are many (60) more citations bearing the name of Labeo in the Digest, and a vast number of citations of Labeo in fragments bearing the name of other jurists — the conclusions of Capito's school seem, in a majority of