Page:Early Greek philosophy by John Burnet, 3rd edition, 1920.djvu/160

From Wikisource
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This page has been proofread, but needs to be validated.
146
EARLY GREEK PHILOSOPHY

wards after having nourished the flame. It follows that the whole of reality is like an ever-flowing stream, and that nothing is ever at rest for a moment. The substance of the things we see is in constant change. Even as we look at them, some of the stuff of which they are composed has already passed into something else, while fresh stuff has come into them from another source. This is usually summed up, appropriately enough, in the phrase "All things are flowing" (πάντα ῥεῖ), though this does not seem to be a quotation from Herakleitos. Plato, however, expresses the idea quite clearly. "Nothing ever is, everything is becoming"; "All things are in motion like streams"; "All things are passing, and nothing abides"; "Herakleitos says somewhere that all things pass and naught abides; and, comparing things to the current of a river, he says you cannot step twice into the same stream" (cf. fr. 41)—these are the terms in which he describes the system. And Aristotle says the same thing, "All things are in motion," "nothing steadfastly is."[1] Herakleitos held, in fact, that any given thing, however stable in appearance, was merely a section in the stream, and that the stuff composing it was never the same in any two consecutive moments. We shall see presently how he conceived the process to operate; meanwhile we remark that this is not the most original feature of the system. The Milesians had held a similar view.

71.The Upward and Downward path. Herakleitos appears to have worked out the details with reference to the theories of Anaximenes.[2] It is unlikely, however, that he explained the transformations of matter by means of rarefaction and condensation.[3] Theophrastos, it appears, suggested that he did; but he allowed it was by no means clear. The passage from Diogenes we are about to quote has faithfully preserved this touch.[4] In the

  1. Plato, Theaet. 152 e 1; Crat. 401 d 5, 402 a 8; Arist. Top. A, 11. 104 b 22 ; De caelo, Γ, 1. 298 b 30; Phys. Θ, 3. 253 b 2.
  2. See above, Chap. I. § 29.
  3. See, however, the remark of Diels (Dox. p. 165) quoted R.P. 36 c.
  4. Diog. ix. 8, σαφῶς δ' οὐθὲν ἐκτίθεται.