ANSELM,
Archbishop of
Canterbury, was born in
1033, at or near
Aosta, in
Piedmont. His family was accounted noble, and was possessed of considerable
property. Gundulph, his father, was by birth a
Lombard, and seems to have been a man of harsh and violent temper; his mother, Ermenberga, was a prudent and virtuous woman, from whose careful religious training the young Anselm derived much benefit. At the early age of fifteen he desired to devote himself to the service of
God by entering a convent, but he could not obtain his father’s consent. Disappointment brought on an
illness, on his recovery from which he seems for a time to have given up his studies, and to have plunged into the gay life of the world. During this time his mother died, and his father’s harshness became unbearable. He left home, and with only one attendant crossed the
Alps, and wandered through
Burgundy and
France. Attracted by the fame of his countryman,
Lanfranc, then
prior of
Bec, he entered
Normandy, and, after spending some time at
Avranches, settled at the
monastery of
Bec. There, at the age of twenty-seven, he became a
monk; three years later, when
Lanfranc was promoted to the
abbacy of
Caen, he was elected
prior. This office he held for fifteen years, and then, in
1078, on the death of
Herluin, the warrior monk who had founded the
monastery, he was made
abbot. Under his rule
Bec became the first seat of learning in
Europe, a result due not more to his intellectual powers than to the great moral influence of his noble character, and his loving, kindly discipline. It was during these quiet years at
Bec that Anselm wrote his first
philosophical and
religious works, the
dialogues on
Truth and
Freewill, and the two celebrated treatises, the
Monologion and
Proslogion. Meanwhile the convent had been growing in wealth, as well as in reputation, and had acquired considerable
property in
England, which it became the duty of Anselm occasionally to visit. By his mildness of temper and unswerving rectitude, he so endeared himself to the
English that he was looked upon and desired as the natural successor to
Lanfranc, then
archbishop of
Canterbury. But on the death of that great man, the ruling sovereign,
William Rufus, seized the possessions and revenues of the
see, and made no new appointment. About four years after, in
1092, on the invitation of
Hugh,
earl of
Chester, Anselm with some reluctance, for he feared to be made
archbishop, crossed to
England. He was detained by business for nearly four
months, and when about to return, was refused permission by the king. In the following year
William fell ill, and thought his
death was at hand. Eager to make
atonement for his
sin with regard to the
archbishopric, he nominated Anselm to the vacant
see, and, after a great struggle, compelled him to accept the
pastoral staff of office. After obtaining
dispensation from his duties in
Normandy, Anselm was
consecrated in
1093. He demanded of the king, as the conditions of his retaining office, that he should give up all the possessions of the
see, accept his spiritual counsel, and acknowledge
Urban as
Pope in opposition to the
anti-pope,
Clement. He only obtained a partial consent to the first of these, and the last involved him in a serious difficulty with the king. It was a
rule of the church that the
consecration of
metropolitans could not be completed without their receiving from the hands of the
Pope the
Pallium, or
robe. Anselm, accordingly, insisted that he must proceed to
Rome to receive the
pall. But
William would not permit this; he had not acknowledged
Urban, and he maintained his right to prevent any
Pope being acknowledged by an
English subject without his permission. A great
council of churchmen and nobles, held to settle the matter, advised Anselm to submit to the king, but failed to overcome his mild and patient firmness. The matter was postponed, and
William meanwhile privately sent messengers to
Rome, who acknowledged
Urban and prevailed on him to send a
legate to the king bearing the
archiepiscopal pall. A partial reconciliation was then effected, and the matter of the
pall was compromised. It was not given by the king, but was laid on the
altar at
Canterbury, whence Anselm took it. Little more than a
year after, fresh trouble arose with the king, and Anselm resolved to proceed to
Rome and seek the counsel of his
spiritual father.
With great difficulty he obtained a reluctant permission to leave, and in
October 1097 he set out for
Rome. William immediately seized on the
revenues of the
see, and retained them to his death. Anselm was received with high honour by
Urban, and at a great
council held at
Bari, he was put forward to defend the
Latin doctrine of the
Holy Ghost against the objections of the
Greek Church. But
Urban was too politic to embroil himself with the king of
England, and Anselm found that he could obtain no substantial result. He withdrew from
Rome, and spent some time at the little
village of
Schlavia. Here he finished his treatise on the
atonement,
Cur Deus homo, and then retired to
Lyons. In
1100 William was killed, and
Henry, his successor, at once recalled Anselm. But
Henry demanded that he should again receive from him in person
investiture in his office of
archbishop, thus making the dignity entirely dependent on the royal
authority. Now, the
Papal rule in the matter was plain; all
homage and
lay investiture were strictly prohibited. Anselm represented this to the king; but
Henry would not relinquish a
privilege possessed by his predecessors, and proposed that the matter should be laid before the
Holy See. The answer of
the Pope reaffirmed the law as to
investiture. A second
embassy was sent, with a similar result.
Henry, however, remained firm, and at last, in
1103, Anselm and an
envoy from the king set out for
Rome. The
Pope,
Paschal, reaffirmed strongly the rule of
investiture, and passed sentence of
excommunication against all who had infringed the law, except
Henry. Practically this left matters as they were, and Anselm, who had received a message forbidding him to return to
England unless on the king’s terms, withdrew to
Lyons, where he waited to see if
Paschal would not take stronger measures. At last, in
1105, he resolved himself to
excommunicate Henry. His intention was made known to the king through his sister, and it seriously alarmed him, for it was a critical period in his affairs. A meeting was arranged, and a reconciliation between them effected. In
1106 Anselm crossed to
England, with power from the
Pope to remove the sentence of
excommunication from the illegally
invested churchmen. In
1107 the long dispute as to
investiture was finally ended by the king resigning his formal
rights. The remaining two years of Anselm’s life were spent in the duties of his
archbishopric. He died 21st
April 1109. His
canonization appears to have taken place in
1494.
Anselm may, with some justice, be considered the first scholastic philosopher and theologian. His only great predecessor, Scotus Erigena, had more of the speculative and mystical element than is consistent with a schoolman; but in Anselm are found that recognition of the relation of reason to revealed truth, and that attempt to elaborate a rational system of faith, which form the special characteristics of scholastic thought. His constant endeavour is to render the contents of the Christian consciousness clear to reason, and to develop the intelligible truths interwoven with the Christian belief. The necessary preliminary for this is the possession of the Christian consciousness. “He who does not believe will not experience; and he who has not experienced will not understand.” That faith must precede knowledge is reiterated by him. “Neque enim quæro intelligere ut credam, sed credo ut intelligam. Nam et hoc credo, quia, nisi credidere, non intelligam.” “Christianus per fidem debet ad intellectum proficere, non per intellectum ad fidem accedere.” “Rectus ordo exigit, ut profunda Christianæ fidei credamus, priusquam ea præsumamus ratione discutere” But after the faith is held fast, the attempt must be made to demonstrate by reason the truth of what we believe. It is wrong not to do so. “Negligentiæ mihi esse videtur, si, postquam confirmati sumus in fide, non studemus quod credimus, intelligere.” To such an extent does he carry this demand for rational explanation that, at times, it seems as if he claimed for unassisted intelligence the power of penetrating even to the mysteries of the Christian faith. On the whole, however, the qualified statement is his real view; merely rational proofs are always, he affirms, to be tested by Scripture. (Cur Deus homo, i. 2 and 38; De Fide Trin. 2.)
The groundwork of his theory of
knowledge is contained in the tract
De Veritate, in which, from the consideration of
truth as in
knowledge, in
willing, and in things, he rises to the affirmation of an absolute truth, in which all other truth participates. This absolute truth is
God himself, who is therefore the ultimate ground or principle both of things and of thought. The notion of
God comes thus into the foreground of the system; before all things it is necessary that it should be made clear to
reason, that it should be demonstrated to have real existence. This demonstration is the substance of the
Monologion and
Proslogion. In the first of these the
proof rests on the ordinary grounds of
realism, and coincides to some extent with the earlier theory of
Augustine, though it is carried out with singular boldness and fulness. Things, he says, are called good in a variety of ways and degrees; this would be impossible if there were not some
absolute standard, some good in itself, in which all relative goods participate. Similarly with such
predicates as great, just; they involve a certain greatness and justice. The very existence of things is impossible without some one Being, by whom they are. This absolute Being, this goodness, justice, greatness, is
God. Anselm was not thoroughly satisfied with this reasoning; it started from
a posteriori grounds, and contained several converging lines of
proof. He desired to have some one short demonstration. Such a demonstration he presented in the
Proslogion; it is his celebrated
ontological proof.
God is that being than whom none greater can be conceived. Now, if that than which nothing greater can be conceived existed only in the
intellect, it would not be the absolutely greatest, for we could add to it existence in reality. It follows, then, that the being than whom nothing greater can be conceived,
i.e. God, necessarily has real existence. This reasoning, in which Anselm partially anticipated the
Cartesian philosophers, has rarely seemed satisfactory. It was opposed at the time by the
monk Gaunilo, in his
Liber pro Insipiente, on the ground that we cannot pass from
idea to
reality. The same criticism is made by several of the later
schoolmen, among others by
Aquinas, and is in substance what
Kant advances against all
ontological proof. Anselm replied to the objections of Gaunilo in his
Liber Apologeticus. The existence of
God being thus held proved, he proceeds to state the rational grounds of the
Christian doctrines of creation and of the
Trinity. With reference to this last, he says we cannot know
God from himself, but only after the analogy of his creatures; and the special analogy used is the self-consciousness of
man, its peculiar double nature, with the necessary elements,
memory and
intelligence, representing the relation of the
Father to the
Son. The mutual
love of these two, proceeding from the relation they hold to one another, symbolizes the
Holy Spirit. The further
theological doctrines of
man,
original sin,
free will, are developed, partly in the
Monologion, partly in other mixed treatises. Finally, in his greatest work,
Cur Deus homo, he undertakes to make plain, even to
infidels, the rational necessity of the
Christian mystery of the
atonement. The theory rests on three positions: that satisfaction is necessary on account of
God’s honour and
justice; that such satisfaction can be given only by the peculiar personality of the God-man; that such satisfaction is really given by the voluntary death of this infinitely valuable person. The demonstration is, in brief, this. All the actions of men are due to the furtherance of
God's glory ; if, then, there be
sin,
i.e., if God's honour be wounded, man of himself can give no satisfaction. But the justice of God demands satisfaction; and as an insult to infinite honour is in itself infinite, the satisfaction must be infinite,
i.e., it must outweigh all that is not God. Such a penalty can only be paid by God himself, and, as a penalty for man, must be paid under the form of man. Satisfaction is only possible through the God-man. Now this God-man, as sinless, is exempt from the punishment of sin; His passion is therefore voluntary, not given as due. The merit of it is therefore infinite; God's justice is thus appeased, and His mercy may extend to man. This theory has exercised immense influence on the form of church doctrine. It is certainly an advance on the older patristic theory, in so far as it substitutes for a contest between God and Satan, a contest between the goodness and justice of God; but it puts the whole relation on a merely legal footing, gives it no ethical bearing, and neglects altogether the consciousness of the individual to be redeemed. In this respect it contrasts unfavourably with the later theory of Abelard.
Anselm's speculations did not receive, in the middle ages, the respect and attention justly their due. This was probably due to their unsystematic character, for they are generally tracts or dialogues on detached questions, not elaborate treatises like the great works of Albert, Aquinas, and Erigena. They have, however, a freshness and philosophical vigour, which more than makes up for their want of system, and which raises them far above the level of most scholastic}} writings.
A full account of Anselm's life is given by Eadmer, Vita Anselmni. His works have been frequently published; the best editions are by Gerberon (containing the life, by Eadmer), Paris, 1675, 2nd ed. 1721; and in Migne, Patrologiæ Cursus Completus, vol. clv.
The Cur Deus homo has been frequently published in a separate form. The Monologion and Proslogion have been translated, with notes, by Bouchitté, Le Rationalisme Chrétien, Paris, 1842. In addition to the copious notices in general histories of theology and philosophy, the following works may be referred to:—Möhler, Anselm, translated into English, 1842; Franck, Anselm von Canterbury, 1842; Hasse, Anselm von Canterbury, I. "Leben," 1843, II. "Philosophie," 1852; Remusat, Anselme de Cantorbéry, 1855, 2d ed. 1868; R. W. Church, St Anselm, 1870.