Page:The religion of Plutarch, a pagan creed of apostolic times; an essay (IA religionofplutar00oakeiala).pdf/152

From Wikisource
Jump to navigation Jump to search
This page needs to be proofread.

adopted by the Pythagoreans in the latter sense,[1] while Plato, who believed in none of these things, had, on one or two occasions, by the use of philosophic "myth" replete with more than Socratic irony, described these beings as playing a part between God and man which might be tolerantly regarded as not greatly dissimilar from that popularly assigned to the lesser deities of the Hellenic Olympus.[2] In the "Statesman," the creation-myth, to which the Stranger invites the

  • [Footnote: der Ægyptischen Mythen von Isis und Osiris geht von der ausdrücklichen

Voraussetzung aus dass diese Gottheiten wesentlich Hellenische sind" (Volkmann, vol. ii. p. 23). But these varying views are simply two different ways of regarding the real fact, which is that Plutarch regards foreign myths and Greek alike as different expressions of the conception of Divine Unity—such Unity not being either Hellenic or Egyptian, but simply absolute (see subsequent analysis of the De Iside et Osiride).]." This libellus I cannot identify with any enumerated in the catalogue of Lamprias.)]

  1. Diogenes Laertius, viii. 32. Ritter and Preller also refer to Apuleius' De Deo Socratis: "Atenim Pythagoricos mirari oppido solitos, si quis se negaret unquam vidisse Dæmonem, satis, ut reor, idoneus auctor est Aristoteles." (Below this passage in my edition of Apuleius (the Delphin, of 1688) appears the note "Idem scribit Plutarch, in libello [Greek: peri thaumasiôn akousmatôn
  2. "Plato, ne Anaxagoræ aut Socratis modo impietatis reus succumberet, præterea ne sanctam animis hebetioribus religionem turbaret, intactos reliquit ritus publicos et communem de diis dæmonibusque opinionem; quæ ipse sentiat, significat quidem, sed, ut solet in rebus minus certis et a mera dialectica alienis, obvoluta fabulis" (Wolff, De Dæmonibus, loc. cit.). Is it permissible to suppose that the third consideration—that expressed in the italicized words—operated more strongly on Plato than either or both of the first two? Aristotle, at any rate, takes up a much firmer attitude in face of the popular mythology, which he regards as fabulously introduced for the purpose of persuading the multitude, enforcing the laws, and benefiting human life (Metaphysics, xi. (xii.) 8, T. Taylor's translation). This famous passage is as outspoken as Epicureanism.